Type Theory: A Modern Computable Paradigm for Math

In several decades, 2013 might be considered mathematically Historical. For an entire year, three dozens of 2013’s greatest minds were gathered at the Institute of Advanced Study in Princeton, with the duty to rethink the foundations of mathematics!

So, was it a success? Did they come out with something interesting?

They surely did! And it’s all contained in a massive 600-page new Bible of mathematics you can download for free! This holy book shatters much of the classical edifices, and redefines many of the most fundamental concepts of mathematics, like equalities. More interestingly, it gives a new powerful paradigm for what mathematics is, and how it should be structured. This paradigm sounds so promising that, in April 2014, the Department of Defense has given Carnegie Mellon a 7.5 million dollar DoD grant to carry on the ideas of this new paradigm!

I didn’t know mathematics needed a makeover…

To understand the importance of redefining the whole endeavor of mathematics, let’s go back a hundred years…

This is the first of a series of 3 articles on homotopy type theory. This first part is restricted to type theory. It is meant to be quite accessible, although it will get increasingly abstract. I’ll try to go through the main ideas without ever diving into major technicalities. The second episode deals with higher inductive types and the third episode will be on the univalence axiom. Subscribe with the box on the right if you don’t want to miss it! I’d like to express my great gratitude for Andrew Cave, who guided me in my journey through homotopy type theory and made important corrections and suggestions to this article.

The Math Foundation Crisis

In 1901, Bertrand Russell (a future winner of the Nobel prize in literature!) annihilated all previous mathematics which a destructive one-line argument. With this single line, he refuted the thousands of pages of (naive) set theory which took decades for Georg Cantor and Gottlob Frege to develop. Thereby, this line also rashly disproved the foundational logic that mathematics was supposed to build upon!

Logicomix is an amazing narrative of the breathtaking drama of the math foundation crisis. I highly recommend you check it out!
Waw! That sounds horrible!

I know! Yet, somehow, the fact that a single line can destroy centuries of thoughts and thousands of books… That’s part of the cruel and unique beauty of mathematics.

OK… But has anyone fixed mathematics since?

Russell tried his best to do so. For decades, he combined his force with Alfred Whitehead to rigorously redefine the foundations of mathematics, which they published in the Principia Mathematica. But that was unbelievably tedious work! For instance, it took 362 pages for them to finally prove the identity $1+1=2$.

362 pages? Really? You’ve gotta be kidding, right?

That was the cost of rigor! To make sure that everything they wrote was perfectly logic, Russell and Whitehead had to patiently verify everything. At least they tried…

Did they not succeed?

It took the greatest logician of all times to prove that they didn’t. In 1931, the young Kurt Gödel crushed Russell’s dreams of a flawless mathematical theory, by proving the famous incompleteness theorems. In short, the first incompleteness theorem states that any mathematical theory including numbers must have claims which can neither be proved nor disproved. Worse, the second proves that no such mathematical theory could ever be proved to be consistent. Naturally, these theorems asserting the impossibility to put mathematics on unshakable grounds led Russell to the following conclusion:

What??? What can we do about mathematics then?

Since then, the most popular foundation of mathematics is a (more consistent) variant of Frege’s naive set theory called the Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) theory. Even though mathematicians have no proof that this theory makes sense, and because they know they’ll never have such a proof, most consider ZF to be true, or, at least, correct. For many, ZF is what current modern mathematics is built upon.

It’s also very usual to add the infamous and controversial axiom of choice to ZF, making it the ZFC theory. The debate over the axiom of choice is also a fascinating one! If you can, please write about it!

Importantly, ZF set theory essentially defines the objects of mathematics as sets, and discusses how they relate with one another through propositions and the infamous membership relationship “$\in$”. However, in the 1950s, an alternative foundational theory called category theory emerged, mainly with the impulsion of the giant Alexander Grothendieck. Interestingly, objects were no longer the core of this foundational theory of mathematics, as asserted by Jean-Pierre Serre:

Hummm… This sounds nearly philosophical…

I guess that searching for the foundations of mathematics, which is the basics of all science, has to be philosophical! After all, it’s about what mathematics is, or, even, what it should be. In fact, a crucial philosophy of mathematics dates back from Luitzen Brouwer. It is called intuitionism, and asserts that the whole endeavor of mathematics is inevitably human-driven. So, mathematics should not be about seeking some absolute Platonic truth that is out there (which was Gödel’s philosophy), but, rather, it should be about what, as humans, we can construct. This effectively gave birth to constructive mathematics, in which all objects must be constructed (or constructible).

Is that any different from ZF or category theory?

Hummm… I’d rather say that ZF and category theory are not really suited for constructive mathematics. A controversial example of a difference between a classical ZF reasoning and a constructive one has to do with the law of excluded middle. This law asserts that what’s not false is true. This leads to Euclid’s famous proof by contradiction: To prove the existence of an object, it suffices to prove that the assumption of its non-existence implies a contradiction. Although this sounds intuitively right, constructive mathematicians instead point out that such proofs do not yield an instance of the existing object. They do not construct the object. For this reason, they are pointless, and we should not do mathematics accordingly to such proofs. Not false is not necessarily synonym to true. I know this sounds counter-intuitive, but, after all, the existence of a third alternative to (provably) true and (provably) false is just the direct implication of Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem.

Waw! I didn’t know logic was that complicated!

It is! And fortunately, type theory draws a clearer picture of the fuzzy world of logic. To do so, roughly, it encapsulates each mathematical theory into a universe. One universe may satisfy the law of excluded middle. But another may not. The beauty of type theory is that it is perfectly fit to describe both.

So, what is type theory?

Crucially, type theory models both objects and the relations between them with types. Thus, a type can be a set or a theorem (or something else). And proving a theorem boils down to constructing a term of the theorem type.

Wait… I’m lost. Didn’t you say that constructive mathematics is incompatible with excluded middle?

Let me clarify something. Construction in type theory is not synonym of constructivism in Brouwer’s intuitionism (this latter is what is usually meant by constructive mathematics). Suppose that we have proved that assuming 10 is the biggest number leads to a contradiction. In other words, the claim that there is no number bigger than 10 us false. Then, Brouwer’s intuitionism asserts that this proof cannot construct a number bigger than 10, and the proof is thus useless. But we can add the law of excluded middle in type theory as a function which (type-theoretically) constructs some number $x$ bigger than 10 from the proof by contradiction. Conversely though, type theory without excluded middle will not enable that construction of $x$ from a proof by contradiction.

OK… What about homotopy type theory now?

Homotopy type theory consists in studying a type theory universe with a single axiom (as opposed to the 8 axioms of ZF theory)! This axiom, which, by the way, is extremely elegant, is called the univalence axiom. Loosely, it asserts that equivalent types are identical. In essence, this builds upon the famous quote by the father of homotopy theory, the great Henri Poincaré:

Amusingly, Henri Poincaré was also both a great opponent to set theory, and, more importantly, the father of homotopy theory. I bet he would have loved homotopy type theory!

Type vs Set Theory

In this article, we won’t get to homotopy type theory. Instead, we’ll focus on type theory, which was first investigated by Bertrand Russell. But it has greatly evolved since, and represents today the main alternative to set theory.

Why do we need an alternative to set theory?

For a long time we didn’t. In fact, by adding or removing the right axioms in set theory, it seemed like we could get all sorts of mathematics, and Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem guarantees that we’ll never find any more consistent alternative foundation theory. So, the point of an alternative foundation theory cannot really be about creating more mathematics, and definitely not about making mathematics more consistent.

So, once again, why do we need an alternative to set theory?

For computational reasons. The rise of computers raised great interest for type theory, because it better fits computational programming. In particular, proofs in type theory are sequences of instructions, which can be implemented and checked computationally, hence guaranteeing their validity. This computationally-checkable new paradigm may revolutionize the way mathematics is done! In fact, I’m guessing that 22nd Century mathematicians will look down on us and wonder how we ever did maths without this paradigm, just like we (or, at least, I) wonder how 20th Century mathematicians managed to write books without text editors!

I should say that set theory does have its own implementations, like in the Mizar project. But the language developed by type theory has the advantage to be closer to informal mathematics, hence facilitating the task of writing formal mathematics.
Really? What about peer-reviewed mathematics like in the old days?

Modern mathematics now regularly faces proofs that only a handful of mathematicians can (or is willing to) verify, like in the examples of Hilbert’s 16th problem or Mochizuki’s ABC conjecture proof. This has been particularly the case in computerized proofs like those of the 4 color theorem, the Kepler conjecture or this recently found wikipedia-size proof. Meanwhile, checking proofs of the Millenium prize problems require years, and, in many cases, flaws end up revealed. Plus, while it’s definitely important for proofs to drive our intuitions, we also have to acknowledge the fact that some proofs are simply beyond human comprehension, and it may be relevant enough to merely know that they are correct.

Hummm… Why can’t we check set theoretical proofs instead of reinventing type theory?

Because set theoretical proofs are really not adapted to computation, mainly because many sentences in set theory are meaningless. This lack of structure within set theory means that programming it would be like writing codes without programming structures. It’d be messy, uncorrectable and nearly impossible to build upon.

But, using type theory, is it feasible to actually write computationally-checkable proofs?

I’ve never done that… But the authors of the book have successfully computationally checked all the proofs of their 600-page book! And, what I can assure you, is that many of these proofs are very nontrivial modern mathematics proofs! Plus, I guess that they have laid out most of the groundwork, and it will then be easier for others to build upon that. There’s an analogy here with what the first programmers did for computer science, as they wrote the hardcore basic Assembler codes others have built upon since.

Waw! Type theory does sound promising!

It is! But its practicality isn’t the nicest fact about it! What’s much more important, at least to me, is that (homotopy) type theory yields a beautiful different perspective on mathematics.

So what is it about?

Hehe…

Types

Type theory is a huge abstract lego game, which aims at constructing terms of (interesting) types from other already constructed terms. For instance, terms of the type $\mathbb N$ of natural numbers are constructed either as the term $0:\mathbb N$, or as a successor $\mathsf{succ}(n):\mathbb N$ of some already constructed term $n \in \mathbb N$. This means that, to construct the number $2: \mathbb N$, we need to start from $0: \mathbb N$, then construct $1 :\equiv \mathsf{succ}(0) : \mathbb N$, and then $2 :\equiv \mathsf{succ}(1) \equiv \mathsf{succ}(\mathsf{succ}(0)) : \mathbb N$.

The symbol “$1:\equiv \mathsf{succ}(0)$” means that we define (or name) 1 as the constructed term $\mathsf{succ}(0)$.
How is the type theoretical expression $x: \mathbb N$ any different from the set theoretical $x \in \mathbb N$?

There are plenty of subtle differences I won’t dwell on too much here. But, most importantly, saying $x: \mathbb N$ means that $x$ is by definition the result of a finite construction like the one above. In fact, it’s useful to consider that the letter $x$ stands for the entire construction, and not merely as the result of its construction.

Another important difference, which will hold for the difference between “$\equiv$” and “$=$” too, is that an expression $a:A$ can only hold by definition. In particular, it cannot be proved false, and can thus not be the consequence of a theorem.

Now, constructing terms is nice, but it’s useless unless we know how to manipulate them. Thus, while constructors of natural numbers are functions $? \rightarrow \mathbb N$ which output a (new) number, as in $\mathsf{succ} : \mathbb N \rightarrow \mathbb N$, we also need to determine how we can define functions $\mathbb N \rightarrow ?$ which input natural numbers. This way to define outgoing functions is called the induction principle (or elimination principle, or recursion principle).

There’s a slight technical difference between induction and recursion, but I won’t go into details here.
Can you give an example of an induction principle?

Sure! For instance, to define a function $f : \mathbb N \rightarrow \mathbb R$, we are going to need to construct the images $f(0)$, $f(1)$, $f(2)$… successively. This will be very similar to the way we constructed $0$, $1$, $2$… themselves. First, we need to determine the first term $f(0) : \mathbb R$. Second, we need to define how $f$ uses the value $f(n): \mathbb R$ obtained for $n : \mathbb N$ to compute $f(\mathsf{succ}(n)) : \mathbb R$. Calling $g : \mathbb R \rightarrow \mathbb R$ the function which defines the next term, we have $f(\mathsf{succ}(n)) :\equiv g(f(n))$. The data $f(0):\mathbb R$ and $g : \mathbb R \rightarrow \mathbb R$ then define the function $f$.

Formally, we have defined the constructor $\mathsf{rec} : (\mathbb R \times (\mathbb R \rightarrow \mathbb R)) \rightarrow (\mathbb N \rightarrow \mathbb R)$ of functions $\mathbb N \rightarrow \mathbb R$. Now, you might be worried at this point that real sequences can only be these defined by $u_0$ and $u_{n+1} = g(u_n)$, with $g : \mathbb R \rightarrow \mathbb R$. But the above induction principle works if we replace $\mathbb R$ by any type. In fact, this output type may even depend on $n: \mathbb N$. So, for instance, we could first construct a function $h$ which maps integers $n:\mathbb N$ to some element $(n, u_0, u_1, …, u_n) : \mathbb N \times \mathbb R^{n+1}$. By doing so, the induction principle can use all the terms $u_0, …, u_n$ and $n$ to compute $h(n+1)$. Finally, to retrieve the sequence $u$, we merely need to project $h$ to its last coordinate, hence obtaining $u : \mathbb N \rightarrow \mathbb R$. Also, I should say that the type $\mathbb R$ of real numbers may not be the one you’re thinking about…

Let me finish this section by a figure which recapitulates what characterizes a type.

Definitional Equalities

Now, following Poincaré’s quote, mathematics mainly boils down to determining what (different) constructions can be given the same name.

That sounds so abstract…

So let me give you an example. Let’s compare the constructions of $2: \mathbb N$ and $1+1: \mathbb N$:

As it turns out, in this case, the two constructions are somehow equivalent.

You mean, we have $1+1=2$…

Yes. To prove that, we need to get to the definition of addition. There are actually many ways to do so. One way consists in defining $\mathsf{add}(m,n)$ using the induction principle on $n:\mathbb N$.

What does that mean?

We need a first term which we defined by $\mathsf{add}(m,0) :\equiv m$. Then, given $x \equiv \mathsf{add}(m,n)$, we construct the next term by $\mathsf{add}(m, \mathsf{succ}(n)) :\equiv \mathsf{succ}(x)$. This corresponds to using the function $g \equiv \mathsf{succ} : \mathbb N \rightarrow \mathbb N$ to construct next terms in the sequence $\mathsf{add}(m,0)$, $\mathsf{add}(m,1)$, $\mathsf{add}(m,2)$…

Waw! I didn’t know addition was that complicated! How do we then derive $1+1=2$ from that?

In the sum $1+1$, $m$ has been replaced by $1$ and $n$ by $1$. We now use the induction principle. Since $1$ is the successor of $0$, we are in the second case of the definition of $\mathsf{add}$. Therefore, we have $\mathsf{add}(1,1) \equiv \mathsf{add}(1, \mathsf{succ}(0)) :\equiv \mathsf{succ}( x )$, where $x \equiv \mathsf{add}(1,0)$. Yet, to compute $\mathsf{add}(1,0)$, we find ourselves in the first case of the induction principle. Hence, $x \equiv \mathsf{add}(1,0) :\equiv 1$. Therefore, $\mathsf{add}(1,1) \equiv \mathsf{succ}(x) \equiv \mathsf{succ}(1)$. This last term is, by construction, 2. Therefore, we have $1+1 \equiv 2$.

Identity Types

Wait a minute… Is there a difference between $1+1 \equiv 2$ and $1+1 = 2$?

Yes. A big one. The definitional equality $1+1 \equiv 2$ holds by construction. In other words, it says that the sequence of constructions involved in defining $1+1$ is exactly the same as the one for $2$. However, and that’s where things get tricky, the propositional identity $1+1=2$ is actually a type, with possibly terms belonging to it. Crucially, as opposed to definitional equalities, an identity can be proved (or disproved, by that’s much trickier!). To prove an identity, we need to construct one of its terms.

Wait… What does that even mean? What would a term of the identity type “$1+1=2$” be like?

Terms of identity types are called proof or witnesses (or, as we’ll see,  paths). Now, naturally, the simplest kind of proof is the one that asserts that two identical constructions are equal. For instance, since by construction $1\equiv 1$, we have a proof $\mathsf{refl}_1$ of the type $1 = 1$, and we can write that fact compactly as $\mathsf{refl}_1: (1=1)$ (parentheses are usually dropped). Similarly, since $1+1 \equiv 2$, we have a proof $\mathsf{refl}_2 : 1+1=2$. Finally!

Hummm… I don’t really see the point of identity types…

This will enable us to prove many more things! For instance, let’s prove that $0+n=n$ for all $n:\mathbb N$. To do so, for all $n:\mathbb N$, we need to construct a proof $f(n)$ of the type $0+n=n$.

Isn’t it stupidly obvious?

Obvious” is a dangerous word in foundational mathematics!

Hummm… Then I’m lost…

Don’t worry, I’ll go slowly. To prove $0+n=n$, once again, we are going to use the induction principle of $\mathbb N$ to construct the function $f$ which maps $n:\mathbb N$ with a proof $f(n):0+n=n$. Recall that to construct such a function, we need to specify its first term $f(0)$ and a way to construct the terms $f(\mathsf{succ}(n))$ from $f(n)$.

OK… Sounds good.

The first term $f(0)$ needs to belong to the identity type $0+0 = 0$. Using the definition of addition, we know that $\mathsf{add}(0,0) :\equiv 0$, thus, by definition, we have $0+0 \equiv 0$. Now, we use the fact that identical constructions yield a proof of the identity types. This gives us a proof $f(0) :\equiv \mathsf{refl}_0$ of $0+0 = 0$. Our first term of the function $f$ has been successfully constructed!

Awesome! Now we need to construct $f(n+1)$ from $f(n)$.

Exactly! By induction, we are given a successfully constructed term $f(n) : 0+n=n$. Now, notice that $\mathsf{add}(0,\mathsf{succ}(n)) :\equiv \mathsf{succ}(\mathsf{add}(0, n)) \equiv \mathsf{succ}(0+n)$. Thus, by replacing each side by definitionally equal terms, the identity type $0+\mathsf{succ}(n) = \mathsf{succ}(n)$ is actually definitionally equal to the identity type $\mathsf{succ}(0+n) = \mathsf{succ}(n)$. Now, intuitively, if $0+n$ is equal to $n$, then applying some function to both preserves equality.

Please say that this intuition is right!

It’s actually the essence of the propositional identity. More precisely, it is an immediate consequence of the induction principle of identity types: If there is a proof $p$ that $x = y$, then, for any function $g$, we can construct a proof $q$ that $g(x) = g(y)$. The property is known as the lemma of action on path. Now, don’t forget that $x$ and $y$ (and $p$) stand for constructions, and that $g(x)$ and $g(y)$ simply consists in adding one step in these construction. Then, visually, the action of path corresponds to the following figure:

The constructed proof $q$ is denoted $\mathsf{ap}_g(p)$, or, more simply but slightly ambiguously, $g(p)$. In our case, formally, we will define $f(\mathsf{succ}(n)) :\equiv \mathsf{ap}_{\mathsf{succ}}(f(n))$.

Let’s conclude our proof that $0+n=n$. We have given a proof $f(0): 0+0=0$. Plus, using action on path, we have shown how to construct a proof $f(\mathsf{succ}(n)) : \mathsf{succ}(0+n) = \mathsf{succ}(n)$ from a proof $f(n) : 0+n=n$. Thus, using the induction principle of the type $\mathbb N$, we have constructed the function $f$ which maps each natural number $n$ to a proof of $0+n=n$. Woohoo!

Haven’t we done a proof by induction?

This is exactly what we did. And amusingly, in type theory, using propositional identities, proof by induction is merely a case of function construction.

Find out about funnier examples in my article on proof by induction.

Logic

Now, what the example tells us is that logical implications can merely be regarded as functions. After all, to prove that $n:\mathbb N$ implies $0+n=n$, we constructed of a function $f$ that inputs $n$ and outputs a proof of the identity type $0+n=n$. More generally, type theory considers that a type $A$ is true if and only if it is inhabited by a term $a:A$. Then, the logical implication $A \Rightarrow B$ perfectly matches the existence of a function $f: A \rightarrow B$ which constructs a term of $B$ (and thus proves $B$) from a term of $A$ (and hence the assumption that $A$ is true).

What about the logical constructors “and” and “or”?

They have type theoretical translations too! The logical expression “$A$ and $B$” corresponds to the type $A \times B$ called product. Meanwhile the logical proposition “$A$ or $B$” resembles the type $A + B$ called coproduct. This coproduct is to the set-theoretical disjoint union of $A$ and $B$.

Like in category theory, it makes little sense to define unions and intersections in type theory. They are rather replaced by pullbacks and pushouts.
What about negations?

Negations are very tricky. In fact, constructive mathematics avoids negations, mainly because negations are not… constructive! Formally, the negation of a type $A$ is defined as $\neg A :\equiv (A \rightarrow {\bf 0})$, where $\bf 0$ is the type with no constructor. In other words, a type $A$ is false if proofs of $A$ imply a construction of an element of the empty type $\bf 0$ (also known as a contradiction). With this definition, you can still prove that non-$A$ and non-$B$ is equivalent to non-($A$ or $B$). But…

But what?

You can no longer prove the other Morgan’s laws. In particular, there is no proof that non-($A$ and $B$) implies non-$A$ or non-$B$. In fact, crucially, it is no longer the case that the non-inexistence of an object implies its existence. More precisely, there is no proof that $\neg \neg A \rightarrow A$ for all types $A$.

What? That’s just stupid!

Is it though? The beauty of mathematics is to question with reason the simplest facts that we believe to be intuitively obvious. And the last century of logic indicates that many such intuitive obviousness are at best unjustifiable, if not wrong. Today’s greatest minds have long thought it through, and concluded that we shouldn’t blindly believe that not-untrue claims are true…

Wait… You did say that type theory was compatible with classical maths, didn’t you?

Yes. To make it compatible, we simply need to add an axiom $\mathsf{LEM}$ for the law of excluded middle. For any type $A$, this axiom yields a proof $\mathsf{LEM}(A) : \neg \neg A \rightarrow A$. This proof (type-theoretically) constructs an element of $A$ from its double negation. In other words, once we’ve finished a proof by contradiction that some object exists, then $\mathsf{LEM}$ gives us an example of that object.

In this form, $\mathsf{LEM}$ is actually incompatible with the univalence axiom which we’ll get to in part 3 of this series. However, a weaker (and more conform) version called $\mathsf{LEM}_{-1}$ does yield the classical mathematics we are used to, while being compatible with the univalence axiom. Similarly, the axiom of choice is defined as a function $\mathsf{AC}$.
What about quantifiers?

First-order logic in set theory defines two different quantifiers which are essential to mathematics. First is the symbol $\forall$ which reads “for all”, and which we used when we claimed that for all $n : \mathbb N$, we have $0+n=n$. There’s a type-theoretical way to say that. We say that the infinite product type $\prod_{n:\mathbb N} (0+n=n)$ is inhabited. But, in addition to a proposition of logic, it’s useful to regard this infinite product as the type of functions which input $n:\mathbb N$ and output a term (or, in this, a proof) of $0+n=n$.

What about the existential quantifier?

Can’t you guess? The universal quantifier “$\forall$” corresponds to generalizing the product to infinite product. Similarly, the existential quantifier “$\exists$” in phrases like “there exists $n:\mathbb N$ such that $1+n=2$” corresponds to claiming that one of the types $1+n=2$ is inhabited. This can be expressed as the fact that the infinite coproduct type $\sum_{n:\mathbb N} (1+n=2)$ is inhabited.

As an exercise, I’ll let you decipher and prove that $\prod_{n:\mathbb N} \prod_{m : \mathbb N} \sum_{k \in \mathbb N} ((n+k=m) + (n=m+k))$. Also, I should note that the coproduct “$\sum$” is not exactly the same as the existential quantifier “$\exists$”, because the former sort of retrieves information about which term satisfies the property associated to the quantifier. But it’d take a while to highlight this difference…

Let’s Sum Up

It’s always hard to predict the importance of a new theory. Only time will tell. However, if I were to venture on a guess, I’d say that (homotopy) type theory will be a major cornerstone of 21st Century mathematics. I believe that its formalism will trigger a dialog with computers, which, in decades to come, will guide our quest for new insights into the breathtaking world of mathematics. Now, type theory is already pretty cool, but things become even more awesome if you add a homotopy dimension to it! For instance, the last chapter of the book redefines real numbers in a much more convincing way than any other theory ever has before. At least, that’s what the authors of the book claim, and I’m very tempted to believe them.

Can you sum up homotopy type theory in one sentence?

I’ll try! In one sentence, homotopy type theory is a beautiful attempt to formally redefine the whole mathematical endeavor in a way that is both much closer to how informal mathematics is actually done and to how mathematics should be implemented to be computationally checkable. It builds upon type theory, which asserts that both mathematical objects and their relations can be encapsulated in the concept of type.

So, does homotopy type theory offer much more than type theory?

For sure! Crucially, homotopy type theory allows much more freedom in the construction of types, by effectively constructing (and allowing) different proofs of a single (identity) type. But to get there, you’ll need to check the second part of the series!

More on Science4All

Self-Reference, Math Foundations and Gödel's Incompleteness Self-Reference, Math Foundations and Gödel's Incompleteness
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2016-02 | Views: 6716
Although highly appreciated by artists, self-reference has been a nightmare for mathematicians. It took one of the greatest, Kurt Gödel, to provide a better understanding of it. This article deals with paradoxes, recursion, fractals and Gödel's incompleteness theorems.

Construction and Definition of Numbers Construction and Definition of Numbers
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2016-02 | Views: 9289
Although they have been used for thousands of years, an actual definition of numbers was given less than a century ago! From the most fundamental level of set theory, this article takes you to the journey of the construction of natural, integer, rational, real and complex numbers.

Numbers and Constructibility Numbers and Constructibility
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2016-02 | Views: 9568
Last summer, I got to discover Morellet's artwork on inclined grids. Amazingly, this artwork is a display of the irrationality of $\sqrt{2}$! It's also a strong argument for the existence of this number. In this article, after discussing that, I take readers further by discussing what numbers can be constructed geometrically, algebraically, analytically or set theoretically using the power of mathematics!

Proof by Mathematical Induction Proof by Mathematical Induction
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2015-12 | Views: 6715
This article explores the potency of proofs by induction with 4 different stunning puzzles, from a lock puzzle and a lion issue, to the monk problem and the pencil conundrum!

The Limitless Vertigo of Cantor's Infinite The Limitless Vertigo of Cantor's Infinite
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2015-12 | Views: 4152
No one believed him. Not even fellow mathematicians. They thought he was wrong. They thought he was crazy. Even he ended up doubting himself and went crazy. And yet, he had mathematically proved it all. Georg Cantor had figured out how to manipulate the infinite. Even more remarkable, he showed that there were actually several infinities; and some are bigger than others!

Homotopy Type Theory and Higher Inductive Types Homotopy Type Theory and Higher Inductive Types
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2015-12 | Views: 8493
In this article, we explore the possibilities allowed by higher inductive types. They enable a much more intuitive formalization of integers and new mind-blowing definitions of the (homotopical) circle and sphere.

Univalent Foundations of Mathematics Univalent Foundations of Mathematics
By Lê Nguyên Hoang | Updated:2015-12 | Prerequisites: Type Theory: A Modern Computable Paradigm for Math, Homotopy Type Theory and Higher Inductive Types | Views: 4344
In an effort to make mathematics more computable, a consortium of today's greatest mathematicians have laid out new foundations. Amazingly, they all lie upon one single axiom, called univalence. The goal of this axiom is to make formal mathematics more similar to informal mathematics. With univalence, our Arabic numbers aren't just like natural numbers; They are natural numbers. Univalence also has unforeseen and mesmerizing consequences.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *